Changes

From Nordan Symposia
Jump to navigationJump to search
93 bytes removed ,  13:49, 20 December 2020
no edit summary
Line 2: Line 2:  
[[File:Kant bis.jpg|right|frame]]
 
[[File:Kant bis.jpg|right|frame]]
   −
'''Immanuel Kant''' (1724-1804) is one of the most influential philosophers in the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Western_philosophy history of Western philosophy]. His contributions to [[metaphysics]], [[epistemology]], [[ethics]], and [[aesthetics]] have had a profound impact on almost every philosophical movement that followed him. This article focuses on his metaphysics and epistemology in one of his most important works, ''[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Critique_of_Pure_Reason The Critique of Pure Reason]''.  A large part of Kant’s work addresses the question “What can we know?” The answer, if it can be stated simply, is that our [[knowledge]] is constrained to [[mathematics]] and the science of the natural, empirical world. It is impossible, Kant argues, to extend knowledge to the supersensible realm of speculative metaphysics. The reason that knowledge has these constraints, Kant argues, is that the [[mind]] plays an active role in constituting the features of [[experience]] and limiting the mind’s access only to the empirical realm of [[space and time]].
+
'''Immanuel Kant''' (1724–1804), German philosopher. In the ''Critique of Pure Reason'' (1781) he countered Hume's skeptical empiricism by arguing that any [[affirmation]] or [[denial]] regarding the ultimate nature of [[reality]] (“noumenon”) makes no sense. ''His Critique of Practical Reason'' (1788) affirms the [[existence]] of an absolute moral law—the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Categorical_Imperative categorical imperative].
 +
==Description==
 +
He is one of the most influential philosophers in the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Western_philosophy history of Western philosophy]. His contributions to [[metaphysics]], [[epistemology]], [[ethics]], and [[aesthetics]] have had a profound impact on almost every philosophical movement that followed him. This article focuses on his metaphysics and epistemology in one of his most important works, ''[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Critique_of_Pure_Reason The Critique of Pure Reason]''.  A large part of Kant’s work addresses the question “What can we know?” The answer, if it can be stated simply, is that our [[knowledge]] is constrained to [[mathematics]] and the science of the natural, empirical world. It is impossible, Kant argues, to extend knowledge to the supersensible realm of speculative metaphysics. The reason that knowledge has these constraints, Kant argues, is that the [[mind]] plays an active role in constituting the features of [[experience]] and limiting the mind’s access only to the empirical realm of [[space and time]].
    
Kant responded to his predecessors by arguing against the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Empiricists Empiricists] that the mind is not a blank slate that is written upon by the empirical world, and by rejecting the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Rationalists Rationalists]’ notion that pure, a priori knowledge of a mind-independent world was possible.  [[Reason]] itself is structured with forms of experience and categories that give a phenomenal and logical structure to any possible object of empirical experience.  These categories cannot be circumvented to get at a mind-independent world, but they are necessary for experience of spatio-temporal objects with their causal [[behavior]] and logical properties.  These two theses constitute Kant’s famous [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Transcendental_idealism transcendental idealism] and [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Empirical_realism empirical realism].
 
Kant responded to his predecessors by arguing against the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Empiricists Empiricists] that the mind is not a blank slate that is written upon by the empirical world, and by rejecting the [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Rationalists Rationalists]’ notion that pure, a priori knowledge of a mind-independent world was possible.  [[Reason]] itself is structured with forms of experience and categories that give a phenomenal and logical structure to any possible object of empirical experience.  These categories cannot be circumvented to get at a mind-independent world, but they are necessary for experience of spatio-temporal objects with their causal [[behavior]] and logical properties.  These two theses constitute Kant’s famous [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Transcendental_idealism transcendental idealism] and [https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Empirical_realism empirical realism].
Line 12: Line 14:  
#Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Werner Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996.
 
#Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Werner Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1996.
 
#Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. ed. Mary Gregor. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
 
#Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. ed. Mary Gregor. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
#Logic, trans. Robert S. Hartman and Wolfgang Schwarz. New York: Dover Publications, 1974.
  −
#Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science, trans. James Ellington. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1975.
   
#The Metaphysics of Morals. trans. Mary Gregor. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
 
#The Metaphysics of Morals. trans. Mary Gregor. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
#Opus Postumum, ed. Eckart Forster, trans. Eckart Forster and Michael Rosen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
  −
#Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, trans. Gary Hatfield. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
   
#Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone. trans. T.M. Greene and H.H. Hudson. New York: Harper and Row, 1960.
 
#Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone. trans. T.M. Greene and H.H. Hudson. New York: Harper and Row, 1960.
#Theoretical Philosophy, trans. David Walford and Ralf Meerbote. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
+
 
       
[[Category: Philosophy]]
 
[[Category: Philosophy]]

Navigation menu