Changes

From Nordan Symposia
Jump to navigationJump to search
2 bytes added ,  23:35, 12 December 2020
m
Text replacement - "http://" to "https://"
Line 3: Line 3:  
==Etymology==
 
==Etymology==
 
[[Latin]], literally, from the former
 
[[Latin]], literally, from the former
*Date: [http://www.wikipedia.org/wiki/17th_Century 1652]
+
*Date: [https://www.wikipedia.org/wiki/17th_Century 1652]
 
==Definitions==
 
==Definitions==
 
*1 a : [[deductive]]  
 
*1 a : [[deductive]]  
Line 13: Line 13:  
The terms '''''a priori''''' ("prior to") and ''a posteriori'' ("subsequent to") are used in [[philosophy]] ([[epistemology]]) to distinguish two [[types]] of [[knowledge]], justifications or [[arguments]]. A priori knowledge or justification is [[independent]] of [[experience]] (for example 'All bachelors are unmarried'); a posteriori knowledge or justification is dependent on experience or empirical [[evidence]] (for example 'Some bachelors are very happy'). A priori justification makes [[reference]] to [[experience]]; but the issue concerns how one knows the proposition or claim in question—what justifies or grounds one's [[belief]] in it. Galen Strawson wrote that an a priori [[argument]] is one of which "you can see that it is true just lying on your couch. You don't have to get up off your couch and go outside and [[examine]] the way [[things]] are in the [[physical]] world. You don't have to do any [[science]]." There are many [[points of view]] on these two types of assertion, and their [[relationship]] is one of the oldest problems in modern [[philosophy]].
 
The terms '''''a priori''''' ("prior to") and ''a posteriori'' ("subsequent to") are used in [[philosophy]] ([[epistemology]]) to distinguish two [[types]] of [[knowledge]], justifications or [[arguments]]. A priori knowledge or justification is [[independent]] of [[experience]] (for example 'All bachelors are unmarried'); a posteriori knowledge or justification is dependent on experience or empirical [[evidence]] (for example 'Some bachelors are very happy'). A priori justification makes [[reference]] to [[experience]]; but the issue concerns how one knows the proposition or claim in question—what justifies or grounds one's [[belief]] in it. Galen Strawson wrote that an a priori [[argument]] is one of which "you can see that it is true just lying on your couch. You don't have to get up off your couch and go outside and [[examine]] the way [[things]] are in the [[physical]] world. You don't have to do any [[science]]." There are many [[points of view]] on these two types of assertion, and their [[relationship]] is one of the oldest problems in modern [[philosophy]].
   −
See also the related distinctions: [[deductive]]/[[inductive]], [[analytic]]/[[synthetic]], [[necessary]]/[[contingent]].[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/A_priori_and_a_posteriori]
+
See also the related distinctions: [[deductive]]/[[inductive]], [[analytic]]/[[synthetic]], [[necessary]]/[[contingent]].[https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/A_priori_and_a_posteriori]
    
[[Category: Philosophy]]
 
[[Category: Philosophy]]

Navigation menu