Changes

13,643 bytes added ,  17:54, 3 September 2009
no edit summary
Line 68: Line 68:  
:1856 EMERSON Eng. Traits v. Ability, They have solidarity, or responsibleness, and trust in each other.
 
:1856 EMERSON Eng. Traits v. Ability, They have solidarity, or responsibleness, and trust in each other.
 
==Description==
 
==Description==
 +
===Moral Responsibility===
 +
Moral responsibility can refer to two different but related [[things]].
 +
*First, a person has moral responsibility for a situation if that person has an obligation to ensure that something happens. Assume that John promises to baby-sit for his neighbour while she goes to a job interview. However, he decides he will go to a concert instead. Arguably, John has moral responsibility for finding another appropriate babysitter for his neighbour.
 +
*Second, a person has moral responsibility for a situation when it would be correct to morally praise or blame that person for the situation. If John fails to find an appropriate babysitter, then he might be said to have moral responsibility for his neighbour's failure to make her job interview.
 +
 +
People who have moral responsibility for an [[action]] are usually called moral [[agents]]. Agents are [[creatures]] that are capable of reflecting on their situation, forming [[intention]]s about how they will act, and then carrying out that action.
 +
====Moral, causal and legal responsibility====
 +
Moral responsibility is both related to and different from causal responsibility and legal responsibility.[1] People are causally responsible for events when those events are directly brought about by their actions. Often when people have moral responsibility for a situation, they also have causal responsibility for that situation. Someone who is praised for acting in a morally responsible way has usually caused some good state of affairs to occur. To see that a person can have moral responsibility without causal responsibility, however, consider that john might claim that there was nothing in his failure to keep his promise that caused his neighbour to fail to make her job interview. (she could have taken her child with her, or found some other babysitter, for example.) Nevertheless, he may still be morally responsible for her failing to attend the interview. A person is legally responsible for his or her actions when it is that person who will be penalised in the court system for an event that has occurred. Although, it may often be the case that when a person is morally responsible for some act, they are also legally responsible for some act, there are clearly exceptions to this rule. Rules of [[law]] and rules of [[ethics]] do not always overlap.
 +
====Collective moral responsibility====
 +
When people attribute '''moral responsibility''', they usually attribute it to [[individual]] moral [[agents]]. However, Joel Feinberg, among others, has argued that corporations and other groups of people can have what is called ‘collective moral responsibility’ for a state of affairs.[2] For example, when South Africa had an apartheid regime, the country's government might have been said to have had collective moral responsibility for the violation of the rights of non-European South Africans.
 +
====Moral responsibility, free will and determinism====
 +
The [[existence]] of moral responsibility is an important factor in [[philosophical]] [[arguments]] about [[free will]] and [[determinism]].[3] These arguments sometimes begin by assuming that [[human being]]s have moral responsibility, and argue from that premise to the conclusion that humans have [[free will]]. At other times, philosophers who hold that every event is either determined or occurs due to chance have concluded that there is no such thing as moral responsibility.
 +
 +
====Footnotes====
 +
# Klein, Martha. 1995. ‘Responsibility’, In Ted Honderich, (ed.), The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 +
# Risser, David T. 2006. 'Collective Moral Responsibility'. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Accessed 8 Sept 2007)
 +
# Waller, Bruce N. 2005. 'Conditions for Moral Responsibility'. In Consider Ethics: Theory, Readings and Contemporary Issues. New York: Pearson Longman: 215-216, 219-221.
 +
====References====
 +
8Meyer, Susan Sauvé, Chappell, T.D.J. 'Aristotle on Moral Responsibility' . Book review, Mind, New Series, Vol. 105, No. 417 (Jan., 1996), pp. 181-186, Oxford University Press. [1]
 +
*Klein, Martha. 1995. ‘Responsibility’, In Ted Honderich, (ed.), ‘’The Oxford Companion to Philosophy’’. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 +
*Risser, David T. 2006. 'Collective Moral Responsibility'. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy(Accessed 8 Sept 2007)
 +
*Rosebury, Brian, Moral Responsibility and "Moral Luck", The Philosophical Review, Vol. 104, No. 4 (Oct., 1995), pp. 499-524
 +
*Waller, Bruce N. 2005. 'Freedom, Moral Responsibility, and Ethics'. In Consider Ethics: Theory, Readings and Contemporary Issues. New York: Pearson Longman: 215-233.
 +
====External links====
 +
* [http://www.ucl.ac.uk/~uctytho/ted12.htm Free Will, Determinism, and Moral Responsibility - The Whole Thing in Brief] by [[Ted Honderich]]
 +
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-responsibility/ "Moral responsibility"], [[Andrew Eshleman]], [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] (Fall 2004 Edition)
 +
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computing-responsibility/ "Computing and Moral Responsibility"], Kari Gwen Coleman, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
 +
===Responsibility Assumption===
 +
Responsibility Assumption is a doctrine in the [[personal]] growth field holding that each [[individual]] has substantial or total '''responsibility''' for the events and circumstances that befall them in their life. While there is little that is notable about the notion that each person has at least some role in shaping their [[experience]], the doctrine of responsibility assumption posits that the [[individual]]'s mental contribution to his or her own experience is substantially greater than is normally thought. "I must have wanted this" is the type of catchphrase used by adherents of this doctrine when encountering situations, pleasant or unpleasant, to remind them that their own desires and choices led to the present outcome.
 +
 +
The term responsibility assumption thus has a specialized [[meaning]] beyond the general concept of taking responsibility for something, and is not to be confused with the general notion of making an assumption that a [[concept]] such as "responsibility" exists.
 +
====Variations in degree of personal responsibility postulated====
 +
The main variable in the different interpretations of the responsibility assumption doctrine is the degree to which the [[individual]] is considered the cause of his or her own [[experience]], ranging from partial but substantial, to total.
 +
=====Partial but substantial responsibility=====
 +
In its forms positing less than total responsibility, the doctrine appears in nearly all motivational programs, some [[psychotherapy]], and large [[group]] awareness training programs. In programs as non-controversial as [[books]] on the [[power]] of positive [[thinking]], it functions as a [[mechanism]] to point out that each individual does affect the perceived world by the decisions they make each day and by the choices they made in the past. These less absolute forms may be expressed within the rubric that we cannot control the situations that befall us, but we can at least control our [[attitude]]s toward them.
 +
=====Total responsibility=====
 +
In its more [[absolute]] form, the doctrine becomes both more pronounced and more controversial. Perhaps the most prominent dividing line of controversy is the threshold of reversed mental causation, where sufficient responsibility is assigned to the [[individual]] that their [[thoughts]] or mental [[attitude]]s are considered the actual cause of external situations or physical occurrences rather than vice-versa, along the lines of the catchphrase, "[[mind]] over [[matter]]." In this realm the doctrine can present controversial propositions such as, "you chose to have cancer and can just as easily become well if you choose," or the even more shocking and unpalatable proposition, "this genocide took place because the victims wanted to die." Despite the extremity of these positions, there are indeed groups and schools of thought subscribing to the doctrine of responsibility assumption that would support these propositions and more.[1]
 +
====Religious and philosophical roots and usage====
 +
The est seminars popularized the doctrine "responsibility assumption" in the 1970s although they did not explicitly use the term. The doctrine both predates est and is found in a far wider variety of settings. The doctrine has [[spiritual]] roots in the [[monism]] of Eastern religious traditions which hold that only one true [[being]] exists, and all people are one with each other and with god and hence possess Godlike [[power]]s, though they are often unaware of it. It has been likened to [[karma]], which however tends to suggest later retribution for earlier acts, while responsibility assumption posits more of an immediate link between the [[experience]] desired and the outcome received. The doctrine also has associations with the neoplatonist notion of an [[illusory]] world, which the doctrine's adherents would phrase more precisely as an [[illusion]] of external worldly effects on inner mental states. It finds further support in philosophical idealism, which posits [[thought]] as the one true substance.
 +
 +
Among historically Christian churches, denominations have [[belief]] systems that incorporate doctrinal elements similar to responsibility assumption. The doctrine can be found in the work of psychotherapist Georg Groddeck assigning mental causes to physical ailments, has been more recently propagated by self-help authors such as Arnold Patent, and can be found in a number of [[New Age]] and [[new religious movements]]. Prominent among these are [[Christian Science]] and the [[New Thought Movement]], whose constituent theologies espouse mental approaches to bodily healing and express precepts such as, "to each, according to his belief." The doctrine combined with reversed causation can further be found explicitly expressed in works such as [[A Course in Miracles]].
 +
====In popular culture====
 +
The theme of responsibility assumption appears in several places in popular culture. For example, it appeared in Richard Bach's bestseller, ''Jonathan Livingston Seagull'', and Bach addressed the topic more directly in a less-popular later book, ''Illusions''.
 +
[[John Denver]], a proponent of est, wrote two songs about it, ''Farewell Andromeda'' (1973) and ''Looking for Space'' (1975), and the opening lines of ''Farewell Andromeda'' capture the essence of responsibility assumption:
 +
<blockquote>Welcome to my morning, welcome to my day
 +
I'm the one responsible, I made it just this way
 +
To make myself some pictures, see what they might bring
 +
I think I made it perfectly, I wouldn't change a thing</blockquote>
 +
 +
The 1956 movie ''Forbidden Planet'' featured an analogous [[concept]] to responsibility assumption, about a [[race]] who, through technology, became able to materialize their thoughts, to disastrous ends.
 +
 +
The 1967 television series ''The Prisoner'' featured an ambiguous climax spawning several interpretations, one of which implicates responsibility assumption. Throughout the short seventeen-episode series, the eponymous prisoner, a man held against his will by a mysterious [[group]], attempted to determine—and in the final episode apparently succeeded in determining—the [[identity]] of the mysterious [[person]] who led the [[group]] and thus ultimately determined the prisoner's fate. The [[moment]] of [[revelation]] in which the mysterious leader was literally unmasked by the prisoner was brief and unclear, but there are fans of the series who believe the unmasked leader was the prisoner himself.
 +
 +
Though these are prominent examples, varying degrees of the doctrine of responsibility assumption have formed a minor theme more broadly within the United States cultural landscape since the 1960s [[counterculture]].
 +
 +
Generally, different cultures place different weight on [[individual]] responsibility and that this [[difference]] is manifested in [[folklore]]. In this view, the tale of the ''Fisherman'' and the ''Little Goldfish'' (in which the protagonist makes little effort to improve his lot) illustrates the denial of responsibility. In the late 20th century US, the best-selling didactic and allegorical fable ''Who Moved My Cheese?'' underscored personal responsibility for one's livelihood and thus well-being.
 +
====References====
 +
# Espouse total responsibility
 +
:[http://www.mrfire.com/article-archives/new-articles/worlds-most-unusual-therapist.html Dr. Joe Vitale]
 +
:[http://www.landmarkeducation.com/display_content.jsp?top=21&mid=80&bottom=124&siteObjectID=368 Landmark Education at this site states]:
 +
::“Responsibility,” according to The Charter of The Landmark Education Corporation, “begins with the willingness to be cause in the matter of one’s life. Ultimately, it is a context from which one chooses to live.” To be cause in the matter of one’s life is only possible if there are no other causes to which one is ultimately subject.
 +
====Nonfiction====
 +
Anonymous (1992). [[A Course in Miracles]] (2d ed.). Mill Valley, CA: Foundation for Inner Peace. ISBN 0-9606388-8-1.
 +
May, Rollo, and Irvin D. Yalom (1984). "Existential Psychotherapy," pp. 354-391 in Raymond J. Corsini, ed., Current Psychotherapies (3rd ed.). Itasca, IL: Peacock.
 +
====Fiction====
 +
Bach, Richard. ''Illusions—Confessions of a Reluctant Messiah.''
 +
Bach, Richard (1970). ''Jonathan Livingston Seagull''.
 +
[edit]External link
 +
[http://www.christopheravery.com/blog Leadership Personal Responsibility]
 +
 +
[[Category: Philosophy]]
 +
[[Category: Religion]]
 +
[[Category: Psychology]]